I managed to be inadvertently provocative on this subject last time out, with Michael Greve failing to catch my clin d'oeil towards Akhil Amar's anguished declaration that if Obamacare were turned to dust by the U.S. Supreme Court his whole life would be a fraud. In any event, Greve has now explained in some more detail his skepticism about administrative law. This has prompted some (rambling) reflection on my part.
Showing posts with label administrative procedure. Show all posts
Showing posts with label administrative procedure. Show all posts
Saturday, 16 February 2013
Thursday, 20 September 2012
Medical Marijuana and Fettering Discretion
One of the cardinal principles of administrative law is that a decision-maker should never fetter his or her discretion. A recent case involving a claim for reimbursement for medical marijuana illustrates the principle nicely: Heilman v The Workers’ Compensation Board, 2012 SKQB 361.
Saturday, 28 July 2012
Of prerogatives, rules and guidance
The UK Supreme Court decided two very interesting immigration cases the week before last, touching on two very interesting issues.
Friday, 27 July 2012
Principles of (European) Good Administration
The Working Group on EU Administrative Law of Parliament's Committee on Legal Affairs recently reported on the desirability of an EU-wide code of administrative procedure along the lines of America's Administrative Procedure Act (or Ontario's Statutory Powers Procedure Act).
Monday, 9 July 2012
Human Rights Remedies and Administrative Bodies
Unlike many (perhaps most?) other countries, Canada allows administrative bodies to make non-binding interpretations of constitutional provisions and to grant remedies for human rights violations by state actors.
Sunday, 8 July 2012
A Successful Closed-Mind Argument in the Citizenship Setting
A basic principle of administrative law is that a decision-maker must approach its decisions with an open mind. Demonstrating that a decision-maker had a "closed mind", however, is extremely difficult. A decision-maker bent on refusing an application come what may will, if clever enough, keep his or her prejudices to him or herself.
Wednesday, 4 July 2012
Changing Policy to Reflect Policy? Be Careful
As a Q.C., Rabinder Singh appeared in some of the most significant public law cases before the superior courts of England and Wales.
He was appointed to the bench in 2011. From the High Court, he recently issued an interesting judgment in H.A. (Nigeria) v. Home Secretary, [2012] EWHC 979 (Admin), a case concerning the lawfulness of the detention of an asylum seeker who suffered from mental disorders and was detained in a series of Immigration Removal Centres.
Of greatest interest is Singh J.'s treatment of an administrative policy which had been developed by the Home Secretary. The wording of the policy had been changed, but the Home Secretary argued that the change merely reflected administrative practice.
This was important because had the policy changed in substance, it would have been necessary to undertake an equality impact assessment; none had been conducted.
Singh J. held that a material change, requiring an assessment, had occurred, whatever the subjective intention of those involved:
He was appointed to the bench in 2011. From the High Court, he recently issued an interesting judgment in H.A. (Nigeria) v. Home Secretary, [2012] EWHC 979 (Admin), a case concerning the lawfulness of the detention of an asylum seeker who suffered from mental disorders and was detained in a series of Immigration Removal Centres.
Of greatest interest is Singh J.'s treatment of an administrative policy which had been developed by the Home Secretary. The wording of the policy had been changed, but the Home Secretary argued that the change merely reflected administrative practice.
This was important because had the policy changed in substance, it would have been necessary to undertake an equality impact assessment; none had been conducted.
Singh J. held that a material change, requiring an assessment, had occurred, whatever the subjective intention of those involved:
These comments on the interpretation of policies being wholly in the domain of the courts are very English (whenever I get around to my promised discussion of Auer deference, the difference of the American approach will be manifest). But the fundamental point is that when administrative policies change, the administrator in question is placed under a variety of public law duties, which are perilous to ignore.
Friday, 8 June 2012
Due Process and Drone Strikes
Last week, the New York Times published a lengthy article on the 'secret kill list' being maintained by President Obama. Whatever the merits of targeted killings as a matter of international law, international human rights law, or justice, for students of administrative law, there are at least three aspects of interest to the story. To be clear, in what follows, I am not taking a position on the legality or morality of the strikes. But in the absence of formal due process through judicial review, it is worth considering the internal safeguards that administrative law norms suggest.
Thursday, 31 May 2012
Administrative Policies Must be Reasonable
Administrative agencies are generally entitled to develop policies.
Doing so assists agencies in discharging their statutory mandates in a coherent
and consistent manner. Those who come into contact with agencies also benefit:
it ought to be easier to predict the application of a general rule than the
exercise of discretion.
From the Court of Appeal of Saskatchewan comes a reminder that the power
to develop policies is not unlimited. In particular, policies must be
consistent with the statutory provisions they purport to implement.
Tuesday, 22 May 2012
Of Tongues and Teeth: Sliding Scales in Judicial Review
The UK Supreme Court's decision of last week in Humphreys v Revenue Commissioners puts me to thinking about sliding scales. These are quite common in public law. At base, the idea is that greater scrutiny will be paid to decisions (or statutory provisions) in some circumstances, and less in others.
Monetizing Benefits
Interesting paper here from Arden Rowell (University of Illinois). One of the difficulties with regulators performing cost-benefit analyses lies in determining what should go into the analysis. Some things we can count quite easily: to use Rowell's example, the cost of installing rear-view cameras on cars; and the benefits in terms of lives saved (although this exercise may be controversial). Other things are harder, if not impossible, to count: the added benefit that childrens' lives will be disproportionately saved by rear-view cameras. How then, the question goes, can you conduct a cost-benefit analysis when the costs and benefits are incommensurable? Isn't the problem, at base, that regulators must make moral judgments about the weight to accord to certain types of interest, and that moral judgments cannot be quantified? Rowell suggests that regulators should attempt to partially monetize all benefits, as best they can, to conduct thorough cost-benefit analyses in the face of worries about incommensurability:
Insofar as this hesitation stems from concern about the incommensurability of money and other goods, it should cease immediately. Incommensurability does not preclude partial valuation, i.e. the partial expression of a good’s value in terms of another good. Even something as horrific and emotionally laden as the death of a child can therefore be partially monetized, i.e. partially expressed in terms of money, so long as people are willing to pay money to prevent it from occurring. Emotional goods like these are difficult to think about, and even more difficult to monetize, but refusing to monetize them at all is not a reasonable solution.Rowell's solution would have the advantage of forcing regulators to set out their assumptions and judgments in monetary form, so as to allow a balancing of costs and benefits. Such a balancing would then be transparent and accountability would presumably be increased. But I have a nagging feeling that to assign dollar amounts in this way may serve simply to obscure the important moral judgments that have to be made by regulators.
Thursday, 17 May 2012
C’est qui le maître chez l’arbitre?
A
challenge, perhaps, from the Québec Superior Court to the established
rule that tribunals are masters of their own procedures, as long as they do notviolate the rules of natural justice. A challenge, certainly, to anyone who
thinks the distinction in administrative law between matters of procedure (for
reviewing courts) and matters of substance (for decision-makers) is an easy one
to grasp and apply.
Here, four individuals made complaints to a labour
arbitrator. At the outset, the individuals’ union representative successfully
sought an order excluding witnesses from the hearing. Two of the complainants
were to be called and were thus excluded; the two others remained.
Subsequently, however, the union sought to call one of the two complainants who
had sat in on the arbitration up to that point. In addition, it changed representatives
and sought to call the previous representative as a witness. While it is not
clear from the facts, it is possible that the uncomfortable operation of
changing union representatives mid-stream was what led to the difficulties. In
any event, the arbitrator excluded the evidence.
Collier J. reversed the arbitrator’s decision to exclude.
Interestingly, he classified the matter as one of procedural fairness, to which
a standard of correctness should apply. This conclusion is not self-evident. Decisions
on the admissibility of evidence can attract deference, as Lamer C.J. explained
for a majority of the Supreme Court of Canada in Université du Québec à Trois-Rivières v. Larocque (1993):
The question before this Court is…whether, in erroneously deciding to exclude evidence relevant to the ground of dismissal which he has himself identified as being that which he must examine, the arbitrator necessarily commits an excess of jurisdiction. In my view the answer to this question must in general be no. It will be yes, however, if by his erroneous decision the arbitrator was led to infringe the rules of natural justice.
On this analysis, it is only the question of procedural
fairness to which a standard of correctness applies. A standard of
reasonableness applies to the decision-maker’s admissibility determination. In
other words, Lamer C.J. drew a distinction between procedure (correctness) and
substance (reasonableness). In the present case, following this approach, the
questions for the reviewing court would have been (a) was the arbitrator’s
decision to exclude the witnesses reasonable; and (b) did it render the process
unfair?
By contrast, Collier J. asked whether the arbitrator’s
decision to exclude the witnesses was correct, treating it is as a matter of
procedure rather than substance. He examined whether the arbitrator’s
admissibility determination was consistent with the general rule that parties
should not be excluded from hearings. Concluding that it was not, he quashed
the arbitrator’s decision in its entirety.
So much for the arbitrator’s claim to be maître chez lui!
But Collier J. does give a good, sharp explanation of the
standard of correctness:
Like many things, the standard of correctness sounds better
in la langue de Molière.
H/T Ashley Kandestin au Blogue du CRL
80% of life is just showing up
Fascinating decision here from the District Court for the District of Columbia. America's National Labor Relations Board has been at the centre of controversy recently because of President Obama's inability to appoint new members. Before he made recess appointments to restore the full complement of members, the Board took an important decision which would have had the effect of making it easier for unions to become certified for collective bargaining purposes.
But the decision was challenged by a couple of employers' interest groups and ultimately ran aground on the Board's statutory quorum requirement. Three members must "participate" in any decision:
As District Judge Boasberg explained:
As the judge noted, Woody Allen was quite correct to observe that 80% of life is just showing up.
H/T Jonathan Adler at the Volokh Conspiracy.
But the decision was challenged by a couple of employers' interest groups and ultimately ran aground on the Board's statutory quorum requirement. Three members must "participate" in any decision:
But whether the standard is “mere presence” or “participation,” the difficulty is in applying that standard to an online vote. When the very concept of a quorum seems designed for a meeting in which people are physically present in the same place, what does it mean to be present or to participate in a decision that takes place across wires? In other words, how does one draw the line between a present but abstaining voter (who may be counted toward a quorum) and an absent voter (who may not be) when the voting is done electronically?Here, a draft of the proposed rule was circulated by email to all three remaining members. Two indicated an affirmative response. The third never responded, not realizing that his failure to do so would lead to a failure to participate. To no avail, the Board argued that the third member's participation in previous discussions and procedural decisions (in which he had made his opposition clear) and his subsequent release of a statement explaining his opposition satisfied the quorum requirement.
As District Judge Boasberg explained:
[H]e simply did not show up – in any literal or even metaphorical sense. Had he affirmatively expressed his intent to abstain or even acknowledged receipt of the notification, he may well have been legally “present” for the vote and counted in the quorum. Had someone reached out to him to ask for a response, as is the agency’s usual practice where a member has not voted, or had a substantial amount of time passed following the rule’s circulation, moreover, it would have been a closer case. But none of that happened here. In our prior world of in-person meetings, Hayes’s actions are the equivalent of failing to attend, whether because he was unaware of the meeting or for any intentional reason. In any event, his failure to be present or participate means that only two members voted, and the rule was then sent for publication that very day.One other interesting point is the footnoted discussion of the applicability of Chevron deference to the Board's interpretation of its statutory provisions. There is, as the judge noted, an argument that a reviewing court should defer to the Board's determination of whether the quorum requirement has been satisfied: that is, if the Board considers it unnecessary for a formal vote to be recorded, a reviewing court should not interfere. But in the New Process Steel case, the Supreme Court of the United States did not apply Chevron deference to the quorum provision; and, stranger still, the Board did not raise the point in its argument.
As the judge noted, Woody Allen was quite correct to observe that 80% of life is just showing up.
H/T Jonathan Adler at the Volokh Conspiracy.
Tuesday, 15 May 2012
Separate Silos
One of the reasons offered by the concurring judges in Multani for merging administrative review and constitutional review (at least when an individualized decision was challenged) was that keeping them separate and distinct would be confusing to lower courts and litigants. That view never seemed particularly compelling to me: lawyers and judges often make and are faced with arguments that overlap and complement one another.
Interestingly, in Pridgen v. University of Calgary, where students punished for making nasty comments about a professor on a Facebook group successfully sought the quashing of the disciplinary measures against them, two of the judges on the Alberta Court of Appeal expressly avoided dealing with an argument based on the Charter, preferring instead to resolve the case on administrative law grounds. Even Madam Justice Paperny, who dealt with the Charter issue (the tricky part being whether it applies at all to universities), addressed the administrative law argument separately, agreeing that the disciplinary decision was unreasonable.
Her judgment is also notable for its treatment of the reliance by the decision-maker on hearsay evidence. She correctly noted that administrative decision-makers have more leeway than courts in permitting the introduction of hearsay, but that this leeway was exceeded in the present case:
Interestingly, in Pridgen v. University of Calgary, where students punished for making nasty comments about a professor on a Facebook group successfully sought the quashing of the disciplinary measures against them, two of the judges on the Alberta Court of Appeal expressly avoided dealing with an argument based on the Charter, preferring instead to resolve the case on administrative law grounds. Even Madam Justice Paperny, who dealt with the Charter issue (the tricky part being whether it applies at all to universities), addressed the administrative law argument separately, agreeing that the disciplinary decision was unreasonable.
Her judgment is also notable for its treatment of the reliance by the decision-maker on hearsay evidence. She correctly noted that administrative decision-makers have more leeway than courts in permitting the introduction of hearsay, but that this leeway was exceeded in the present case:
Thus in response to the students' argument that the decision did not conform to the University's own guidelines, the University was unable to demonstrate that its reasoning was cogent or that sufficient evidence existed in support of its decision, and its decision was unreasonable.[59] It is generally open to administrative tribunals to admit hearsay evidence. But the relaxation of the rules of evidence does not relieve an administrative decision‑maker of the responsibility to assess the quality of the evidence received in a reasonable manner in order to determine whether it can support the decision being made. And in a subsequent judicial review, the reviewing court must consider whether the decision is “one of a range of possible outcomes”, based on the evidence that was received and assessed by the decision‑maker. It is not an error for a reviewing judge to consider the quality of the evidence and the manner in which it was assessed in conducting that analysis.[60] The evidence on which the University relies is not merely hearsay, it is double or triple hearsay of an extremely vague nature from an unnamed source or sources. It is simply not reasonable to conclude that “injury” within the meaning of the Student Misconduct Policy has been established on the basis of the information provided to the Review Committee, and the chambers judge committed no error in reaching that conclusion.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)